|
{ |
|
"paper_id": "E91-1002", |
|
"header": { |
|
"generated_with": "S2ORC 1.0.0", |
|
"date_generated": "2023-01-19T10:38:09.556614Z" |
|
}, |
|
"title": "COMPARATIVES AND ELLIPSIS", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "S", |
|
"middle": [ |
|
"G" |
|
], |
|
"last": "Puhnan", |
|
"suffix": "", |
|
"affiliation": { |
|
"laboratory": "", |
|
"institution": "University of Cambridge Computer Laboratory SRI International Cambridge Computer Science Research Centre 23 Miller's Yard", |
|
"location": { |
|
"postCode": "CB2 1RQ", |
|
"settlement": "Cambridge" |
|
} |
|
}, |
|
"email": "sgp@cam.sri.com" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": "", |
|
"venue": null, |
|
"identifiers": {}, |
|
"abstract": "This paper analyses the syntax and semantics of English comparatives, and some types of ellipsis. It improves on other recent analyses in the computational linguistics literature in three respects: (i) it uses no tree-or logical-form rewriting devices in building meaning representations (ii) this results in a fully reversible linguistic description, equally suited for analysis or generation (iii) the analysis extends to types of elliptical comparative not elsewhere treated.", |
|
"pdf_parse": { |
|
"paper_id": "E91-1002", |
|
"_pdf_hash": "", |
|
"abstract": [ |
|
{ |
|
"text": "This paper analyses the syntax and semantics of English comparatives, and some types of ellipsis. It improves on other recent analyses in the computational linguistics literature in three respects: (i) it uses no tree-or logical-form rewriting devices in building meaning representations (ii) this results in a fully reversible linguistic description, equally suited for analysis or generation (iii) the analysis extends to types of elliptical comparative not elsewhere treated.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "Abstract", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"body_text": [ |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Many treatments of the English comparative construction have been advanced recently in the computational linguistics literature (e.g. Rayner and Banks, 1989; Ballard, 1988) . This interest reflects the importance of the construction for many natural language applications, especially those concerning access to databases, where it is natural to require information about quantitative differences and limits which are most naturally expressed in terms of comparatives and superlatives.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 134, |
|
"end": 157, |
|
"text": "Rayner and Banks, 1989;", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 158, |
|
"end": 172, |
|
"text": "Ballard, 1988)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "INTRODUCTION", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "However, all of these analyses have their defects (as no doubt does this one). The most pervasive of these defects is one of principle: they all place a high reliance on non-compositional methods (tree or formula rewriting) for assembling the logical forms Of comparatives even in cases that might be thought to be straightforwardly compositional. These devices mean that the grammatical descriptions involved lack, to varying extents, the important property of reversibility: they can only be used to analyse, not to generate, expressions of comparison. This is a serious restriction on the practic,'d usefulness of such analyses.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "INTRODUCTION", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The analysis presented here of the syntax and compositional semantics of the main instances of the English comparative and superlative is intended to provide a fairly theory-neutral 'off the shelf' treatment which can be translated into a range of current grammatical theories. The main theoretical claim is that by factoring out the compositional properties of the construction from the various types of ellipsis also involved, a cleaner treatment can be arrived at which does not need any machinery specific to this construction.. A semantics in terms of generalised quantifiers is proposed.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "INTRODUCTION", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Intuitively, a sentence like:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SYNTAX", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "John owns more horses than Bill owns seems to consist of two sentences ascribing owns ership of horses, together with a comparison of them, where some material has been omitted. Despite appearances, however, this pre-theoretical intuition is ahnost wholly wrong, both syntactically, and, as we shall see, semantically. The sequence 'more horses than Bill owns' is in fact an NP, and a constituent of the main clause, as can be seen from the fact that it can appear as a syntactic subject, and be conjoined with other simple NPs:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SYNTAX", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "[More horses tha~ Bill owns] are sold every day John, Mary, and [more linguists than they could cope with] arrived at the party In order to accommodate example like these we must analyse the whole sequence as an NP, with some internal structure approximately as follows. (We use a simple unification grammar formalism for illustration, with some obvious notational abbreviations).", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SYNTAX", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "A [+comp] NP is one like:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "a nicer horse, a less nice horse, less nice a horse, several horses more several more horses, as many horses, at least 3 mot, I,,:~rses, etc.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "We will not go into details of the internal structure of these NPs, other than to require that whether the comparative element is a determiner or an adjective, the dominating NP carries feature values which characterise it as a comparative NP, and which enforce 'agreement' between comparative pre-and post-particles (er/than,as/as, etc.) via the variable 'P'. We assume that NPs marked as comparative in this way are not permitted elsewhere in the gramnlar.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "In the case of the [+comp] S' constituent, there are several possibilities. Some forms of comparative can be regarded as straightforward examples of unbounded dependency constructions:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "... more horses than Bill ever dreamed he would own _ ... more horses than Bill wanted ~ to run in the race These involve Wh-movement of NPs. The seeond type involving a lnissing determiner dependency:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "John owns more horses than Bill owns _ sheep There were more horses in the field than there were _ sheep.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Rules of the following form will generate [+comp] sentences of this type, using 'gap-threading' to capture the unboullded dependency: As well as these 'movement' colnparatives are those involving ellipsis:", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 42, |
|
"end": 49, |
|
"text": "[+comp]", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "John owns more horses than Bill/Bill does~does Bill/sheep. Name a linguist with more publications than Chomsky. lie looks more intelligent with his glasses off than on.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "It is noteworthy that sentences like the second of these dernonstra.te that the appropriate level at. which ellipsis is recovered is not syntactic, but semantic: there is no syntactic constituent in the first portion of the sentence that could form an appropriate antecedent. We therefore do not attempt to provide a syntactic mechanism for these cases, but rather regard them as containing another instantiation of an S' [7+compJ introdnced by a rule:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "S'[+comp] -> COMP S[+ellipsis, -comp]", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "An elliptical sentence is not a constituent required solely for comparatives, but is needed to account for sentence fragments of various kinds: John, Which house?, Inside, On the table, Difficult to do, John doesn't, He might not want to, etc.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "All of these, as well as more complex sequences of fragments (e.g. 'IBM, tomorrow' in response to 'Where and when are you going?') need to be accommodated in a grammar.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Very many cases of this type of ellipsis can be analysed by allowing an elliptical S to consist of one or more phrases (NP, PP, AdjP, AdvP) or their corresponding lexical categories. Most other commonly occurring patterns can be catered for by allowing verbs which subcategorise for a non-finite VP (modals, auxiliary 'do', 'to') to appear without one, and by adding a special lexical entry for a main verb 'do' which allows it to constitute a complete VP. Depending, of course, on other details of the grammar in question the latter two moves will allow all of the following to be analysed:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Will John?, John won't, He may do, tie may not want to, Is he going to? etc.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "With this treatment of ellipsis, our syntax will be able to analyse all the examples of comparatives above, and many more. It will also, however, accept examples like:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "John owns more horses than inside. Bill is happier than John won't.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "for there is no syntactic connection between tile main clause and the elliptical sentence. We assume that some of these examples may actually be interpretable given the right context: at any rate, it is not the business of syntax to stigmatise them as unacceptable.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Comparatives with adjectives and adverbial phrases, are, mulalis mulandis, exactly analogous to those with NPs, and we omit discussion of them here.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "NP[-comp] -> NP[+comp,postp=P,<feats~,R>] S ' [+comp, postp=P, <feats=R>]", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "In tile interests of fanailiarity the analysis will be presented as far as possible in an 'intensionless Montague' framework: a typed higher order logic. Firstly, we need tile notion of a generalised quantifier. It is well known that most, if not all, complex natural language quantifiers call be expressed as relations between sets. Specifically (Barwise and Cooper, 1981) a quantifier with a restriction R and a body B can be expressed as a relation on the sizes of the set satisfying R, and the set which represents the intersection of the sets satisfying R and B. A quantifier like 'all' can be represented using the relation =, and so a sentence like 'all men are mortal', in a convenient notation, will translate as: quant(~nna.n=m,)~x.man(x),)tx.mortal(x)) (In logical forms, lower case variables will be of type e, and upper case variables will be of type e--~t unless indicated otherwise. All functions are 'curried': thus Sxy.P is equivalent to SxAy.P. Read expressions like 'quant(Q,R,B)' as 'the relation Q holds between the size of the set denoted by R, and the size of the set denoted by Sx.lLx&Bx'. This latter is tile intersection set.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The important thing to note at this point is that the relation Q can be arbitrarily complex, as it needs to be in order to accommodate determiners like 'at least 4 but not more than 7'. The second important thing to notice is that for many quantifiers, we are only interested in the size of the intersection set, and thus tile first lambda variable in Q will be vacuous. Thus 'some' can be expressed as the relation ')mm.m _ 1', as in 'some men snore':", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "quant(,~nnl.m > 1, )~x.man(x)/~x.snore(x))", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "In tile case of the movement types of comparative we can give the semantics in a wholly compositional way by building up generalised quantilters which contain tile comparison. Informally, the gist of the analysis is that in a sentence like 'Jolm owns more horses than Bill owns', there is a generalised quantifier characterising the set of horses that John owns as being greater than the set of horses that Bill owns. hfformally, we can think of the complenaent of a comparative NP as a complex determiner:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "John owns [more than Bill owns] horses (Ill this respect, as in the use of generalised quantifiers, this analysis yields logical forms somewhat similar to those of Rayner and Banks, 1989) . rio build these quantifiers we assume that the various relations signalled by the comparative construction are part of the quantifier. Thus the final analysis of the example sentence is: quant($nm.more(rn, Sx.horse(x)& own(Bill,x)), )~y.horse(y),)~z.own(John,z)) 'More' (or 'less' or 'as') is the relation used to build the quantifier. To avoid notational clutter we call assume that 'more' is 'overloaded', and can take as its arguments either a number, or an expression of type e---,t, in which case it is interpreted as taking the cardinality of the set denoted by that expression. 'More' in fact takes a third argument, which is another quantifier relation. Thus the meaning of a sentence like 'john owns at least 3 more horses than Bill owns' would get a logical form like quant(Anm.more(m,Aab.b_> 3, Ax.horse(x)&own(Bill,x)), Ay.horse(y),Xz.own(john,z))", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 164, |
|
"end": 187, |
|
"text": "Rayner and Banks, 1989)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The way to read this is 'the relation of being more (by a number greater than or equal to 3) than the size of the set of horses owned by Bill, hol:ds of the set of horses owned by John'. Where this extra argument to 'more' is not explicit, we assume it defaults to 'greater than 0'. Itowever, we;shall ignore this refinement in the illustratioias that follow). ~Note that this quantifier is only interested in the intersection set: this is always true of comparative quantifiers.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": ":We now give the meanings of each constituent involved in a couple of examples, along with the relevant rules, in skeletal form. We indicate the trail of gap threading using the 'slash' notation. For the purposes of this illustration we use the analysis of the semantics of unbounded dependencies from Gazdar, Klein, Pullum and Sag (1985): a constituent C containing a gap of category X is of type X---,C. So given a tree of the form [A [B C]] which might normally ],ave as the interpretation of A as B applied to C, the interpretation of a tree [A/X [B C/X]] would be ',~X.B(C(X))'. Since gaps themselves are analysed as identity fimctions this will have the right type. The remainder of the sentence is straightforward. The second example for illustration is:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "John owns more horses than Bill owns. sheep.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "For the subdeletion cases, a fully compositional treatment demands a separate sense entry for 'more', since the Nbar of the NP in which 'more' appears does not occur inside the comparative quantifier:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "APQR.quant (Anm.more(m, Ax.Qx), Ay.Py, Az.Rz)", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "We do not have to multiply syntactic ambiguities: the appropriate sense entry can be selected by passing down into the NP a syntactic feature value indicating whether tile following S' contains an NP or a Det gap. Constituents are assembled as follows: remember that D has the type of ordinary determiners: (e--+t)--,((e---+t)---~t).", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "[ ", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "SEMANTICS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "In order to explain our treatment of ellipsis, we need more about the actual logical forms produced compositionally for sentences. These are the 'quasi logical forms' (QLF) of Alshawi and van Eijck (1989) , differing from 'resolved logical forms' (RLF) in several respects: they contain 'a_terms' representing the memlings of pronouns and other contextually dependent NPs; 'a.fornm' (anaphoric formula) representing the meanings of sentences containing contextually determined predicates (possessives, compound nominals, 'have' 'do' etc); and 'q_terms' representing the meaning of other quantified NPs before the later explicit quantifier scoping phase (see Moran 1988) . QLFs are fleshed out to RLFs via a process of contextually guided inference (Alshawi, 1990) . Since ellipsis is clearly a contextually deternfined aspect of interpretation we extend the 'a_form' construct to provide a QLF for elliptical sentences, and treat the process of interpretation as akin to reference resolution for pronouns.", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 176, |
|
"end": 204, |
|
"text": "Alshawi and van Eijck (1989)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 658, |
|
"end": 669, |
|
"text": "Moran 1988)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"start": 748, |
|
"end": 763, |
|
"text": "(Alshawi, 1990)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ELLIPSIS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Take a sequence like (A) 'Who came.'?' (S) 'John'. We represent the meaning of the 'missing' constituent by an 'a_form' binding a variable of the appropriate type to combine with the meaning of the 'present' constituents to form an expression of the appropriate type for the S' constituent containing the ellipsis. Thus the meaning of the two utterances will be represented as: past(come(who)) a_form(P,P(john))", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ELLIPSIS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "One can think of 'a_form' as asserting that there is such a P: resolution finds *that P. For consistency with the Montague notation we are using we will indicate an 'a_form' variable as a free variable: 'P (john)'.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ELLIPSIS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "for P. In this example the only possibility is that P = Ax.past(come(x)). Thus the meaning of the elliptical sentence after resolution is:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ELLIPSIS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "[Ax.past (come(x))] (john) = past(come(john))", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ELLIPSIS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The theoretical advantages of higher-order unification in the interpretation of ellipsis are amply documented in Dalrymple, Shieber, and Pereira (forthcoming). More details of our own treatment are in Alshawi et hi. (forthcoming) .", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 201, |
|
"end": 229, |
|
"text": "Alshawi et hi. (forthcoming)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ELLIPSIS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "This analysis of inter-sentential ellipsis generalises cleanly to intra~sentential ellipsis, in particular the comparative cases discussed above: the only difference is that location of the 'context' is not trivial, since the ellipsis is, as it were, contained in the logical form that yields the context. As an example, the NP in 'Name a linguist with [more publications than John]' will have a structure:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ELLIPSIS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "[NP [NP more publications] [S' than [S-I-elliptical [NP John]]]]", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ELLIPSIS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "The meaning of the elliptical S will be as above, but the appropriate version of the semantics for the S' rule will (as was the case with the analysis of the movement comparatives given earlier) have to arrange things so that the type of the whole elliptical S' expression is e---*t. Thus the variable representing the ellipsis will be of type e---*(e---~t), assuming that 'john' in this context is of type e. Omitting some of the details, the meaning of the entire NP will then be: AR.quant(Anm.more(m, Ax.publications(x) ~\" [P(john)](x)), Ay.publicatlons(y), Az.R(z))", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ELLIPSIS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "where the meaning of the elliptical S' [P(john)] figures in the second term of the comparison af-The ellipsis resolution method uses a tech-ter beta~reduction. Tile meaning for the whole nique which is formally a restricted type of higher-sentence, again taking some short cuts will he: order unification (Ituet 1975) . Ellipsis resolution proceeds ill three steps. Firstly, we have to find a 'context', which in the case of intersentential ellipsis is the logical form of the preceding utterance. Next, one or more 'parallel' elements are found in this context. In the example above, it would be 'who'. This step is somewhat analogous to the establishing of prououn antecedents, and may be similarly sensitive to properties like agreement, focus, sortal restrictions, etc. When the parallel element(s) have been found, the next step abstracts over the position In reality, of course, the details are more complex than this, but this semi-formal reconstruction should convey the basic principles. Now we have succeeded in analysing all the types of comparative so far discussed using either purely", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 305, |
|
"end": 317, |
|
"text": "(Ituet 1975)", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ELLIPSIS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Morphology, syntax and compositional semantics for NP, AdjP and AdvP comparatives of both movement and ellipsis types have been fully implemented, as well as some other common types of comparative not mentioned here (e.g. Nbar comparatives like 'more men than women'). Ellipsis resolution has been implemented for the inter-sentential cases, but not, at the time of writing, for the intra-sentential cases. However, compositional means, or a non-compositional de-. r . ......... we foresee no problem here, as this is an exten-vlceIor contextuallnterpretatlon ofelhps~s whose . ~ . ....", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "IMPLEMENTATION STATUS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": ". . stun o~ existing mecnamsms. mmn properties, however, are mohvated on grounds other than its use for comparatives. Furthermore, once we have this type of ellipsis mechanism in place, it is a simple matter to extend it to account for comparatives in which the whole comparison is missing:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "\u2022", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "John has 2 more horses. There are at least as many sheep. International. I thank Hiyan Alshawi for his many substantial contributions to the analyses described here, and Jan van Eijck and Manny As Rayner and Banks somewhat ruefully note, Rayner for comments on an earlier draft. these are in many texts by far the most cornmonly encountered form of comparative, although their analysis, in common with others, fails to handle them.", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "\u2022", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Syntactically, what we do is to give the various comparative morphemes an analysis in which they are marked as [-comparative] . Thus a phrase like 'at least as many sheep' will be analysed as either a + or -comparative NP. In the first case, tile syntax will only permit it to occur with an explicit complement, as detailed above, and in the second case the syntax will prevent an explicit complement occurring. Semantically, however, the second contains an elliptical comparison. Thus the meaning of 'more' in this type of comparative will be: AP Q.quant (Anm.more(m, 2x. P(x) & R(x)), ~y.P(y),2z.(Q(z))", |
|
"cite_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 111, |
|
"end": 125, |
|
"text": "[-comparative]", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "\u2022", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "where R represents the meaning of the missing constituent\u2022 In a context where 'John has more", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "\u2022", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"back_matter": [ |
|
{ |
|
"text": "Ax.publications(x) ~ [P(john)](x)), Ay.publlcations(y), Az.have(linguist,z))We now have to find a suitable context for ellipsis resolution. The only candidate expression with an element parallel to 'john' is 'Az.have(linguist,z)'. Abstracting over the parallel element gives us 'Alz.have(l,z)', which is an appropriate candidate for P. After substituting and reducing the final meaning of the whole sentence will be:", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "acknowledgement", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": "This work was supported by the CLARE consortium: BT, BP, the Information Engineering Directorate of the DTI, RSRE Malvern, and SRI", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
}, |
|
{ |
|
"text": " , 1.1, 27-57 . horses' follows a sentence like 'Bill has some horses'~Cloran, D. B. (1988) Quantifier Scoping in R should be resolved to 'ha.have(bill,a)'. Notice that it may be necessary to provide interpretations for 'more' in these contexts corresponding to both the NP-gap and the Det-gap cases: the elliptical portion is different depending on whether the preceding sentence was 'Bill has some horses' or 'Bill has many sheep': the latter is like the Det-gap type of explicit comparison. ", |
|
"cite_spans": [], |
|
"ref_spans": [ |
|
{ |
|
"start": 1, |
|
"end": 13, |
|
"text": ", 1.1, 27-57", |
|
"ref_id": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"eq_spans": [], |
|
"section": "annex", |
|
"sec_num": null |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"bib_entries": { |
|
"BIBREF0": { |
|
"ref_id": "b0", |
|
"title": "al.) forthcoming 'The Core Language Engine", |
|
"authors": [ |
|
{ |
|
"first": "H", |
|
"middle": [], |
|
"last": "Alshawi", |
|
"suffix": "" |
|
} |
|
], |
|
"year": null, |
|
"venue": "", |
|
"volume": "", |
|
"issue": "", |
|
"pages": "", |
|
"other_ids": {}, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"urls": [], |
|
"raw_text": "Alshawi, H. (et al.) forthcoming 'The Core Language Engine', MIT Press.", |
|
"links": null |
|
} |
|
}, |
|
"ref_entries": { |
|
"FIGREF0": { |
|
"text": "comp, gapIn= [CAT [<f eat s=R>] ], gapOut= [] ] (.here CAT is either NP or Det)", |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure" |
|
}, |
|
"FIGREF1": { |
|
"text": "The relevant rules and sense entries in schematic form are: S --* NP VP : NP(VP) VP -. V NP : V(NP) NP -* NP[+comp] S' :NP(S) S' --* Comp S/NP : Ax.S(AP.P(x)) S' -\u00a2 Comp S/Det : Ax.S(APQ.P(x) Ir Q(x)) S/Gap --~ NP VP/Gap : AG.NP(VP(G)) VP/Gap --~ V NP/Gap : AG.V(NP(G)) NP/NP -~ e : AN.N NP/Det -~ Nbar : AD.D(Nbar) NP --~ bill : AP.P(bill) NP -~ Det Nbar : Det(Nbar) Det --~ more : APQIt.quant (Anm.more(m, Ax.Px & Qx),Ay.Py, Az.Rz) Nbar --~ horses : Ax.horse(x) V --* owns : ANx.N(Ay.owns(x,y)) 'Gap' abbreviates either NP[-comp] or Det, and G is a variable of the appropriate type for that constituent. N is an NP type variable; D a Det type variable, as are their primed versions. Notice that comparative determiners and their NPs are of higher type than non-comparative NPs, at least for those analyses which analyse relative clauses as modifiers of Nbar rather than NP. Constituent meanings are assembled by the rules above as follows: [NP+cemp more horses]: AQR.quant (Anm.more(m, Ax.horse(x)&: Q(x)), Ay.horse (y),Az.it(x)) [VP/NP owns ,]: AG.[ANx.N (Ay.owns (x,y))] ([AN'.N'] G) = AG.Ax.G (Ay.owns(x~y)) [S/NP Bill owns el: AG'.[AP.P (bill)/([AG.Ax.G (Ay.owns(x,y))] G') = AG'.G'(Ay.owns (bill,y)) IS' than Bill owns el: = Ax.[AG'.G'(Ay.owns (bill,y)/(AP.P (x)) = Ax.owns(bill,x) [NP [more horses][S' than Bill owns el: AR.quant(Anm.more(m, Ax.horse(x) Y., own(bill,x)), Ay.horse(y),Az.R(z))", |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure" |
|
}, |
|
"FIGREF2": { |
|
"text": "NP/Det e sheep]: AD.D(As.sheep(s)) [VP/Det owns \u2022 sheep]: AD'.[ANx.N(Ay.owns(x,y))] ([AD.D(As.sheep(s))]D') = AD'.Ax.[D' (As.sheep(s))/(Ay.owns(x,y) ) [S/Det Bill owns e sheep]: AD'.([D'(As.sheep(s))] (Ay.own~ (bill,y))) [S' than Bill owns e sheep]-\" Ax.[ AD'.([D' (As.sheep(s))/(Ay.owns (bill,y)) )] (APQ.P(x) ~\" Q(x)) = Ax.sheep(x) & owns{bill,x) [NP+eomp more horses]: AQR.quant (Anm.more(m, Ax.Qx), Ay.horse(y),Az.R(z)) [NP more horses than Bill owns e sheep]: AQIt.[quant(Anm.more (m, Ax.Qx), Ay.horse(y),Az.tt(z))] (Ax.sheep(x) & owns(bill,x)) = AR.quant(Anm.more(m, Ax.sheep(x) ~ owns(bill,x)), Ay.horse(y),Az.It(z)) The final logical form for the whole sentence is: quant(Anm.more(m, Ax.sheep(x) & owns(bill,x)), Ay.horse (y) ,Az.own (john,z))", |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure" |
|
}, |
|
"FIGREF3": { |
|
"text": "(s) of the element(s), and suggests the result as a candidate name(hearer,linguist) & quant(Anm.more(m, name(hearer,linguist) \u00a3z quant (Anm.more(m, Ax.publications(x) ~ have(john,x)), Ay.publications(y), Az.have(llnguist~z))", |
|
"uris": null, |
|
"num": null, |
|
"type_str": "figure" |
|
} |
|
} |
|
} |
|
} |